valid or invalid: “S or R. Not S and Not R. Ergo, B.”












1















“Either it is sunny or it is raining. But now, it is neither sunny nor is it raining. So, the Boston Bruins will win the Stanley Cup this year.”



Is this argument valid or invalid? I’m pretty stumped, but I’m going to say invalid because the premises contradict each other, but I honestly don’t know. Also, in addition to valid and invalid, could you explain why that is the case? Thanks!










share|improve this question









New contributor




A. Delarge is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.





















  • Neither term in the conclusion appears in the premises. It looks like the relationship of the premises to the conclusion is irrelevancy.

    – Mark Andrews
    4 hours ago
















1















“Either it is sunny or it is raining. But now, it is neither sunny nor is it raining. So, the Boston Bruins will win the Stanley Cup this year.”



Is this argument valid or invalid? I’m pretty stumped, but I’m going to say invalid because the premises contradict each other, but I honestly don’t know. Also, in addition to valid and invalid, could you explain why that is the case? Thanks!










share|improve this question









New contributor




A. Delarge is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.





















  • Neither term in the conclusion appears in the premises. It looks like the relationship of the premises to the conclusion is irrelevancy.

    – Mark Andrews
    4 hours ago














1












1








1








“Either it is sunny or it is raining. But now, it is neither sunny nor is it raining. So, the Boston Bruins will win the Stanley Cup this year.”



Is this argument valid or invalid? I’m pretty stumped, but I’m going to say invalid because the premises contradict each other, but I honestly don’t know. Also, in addition to valid and invalid, could you explain why that is the case? Thanks!










share|improve this question









New contributor




A. Delarge is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.












“Either it is sunny or it is raining. But now, it is neither sunny nor is it raining. So, the Boston Bruins will win the Stanley Cup this year.”



Is this argument valid or invalid? I’m pretty stumped, but I’m going to say invalid because the premises contradict each other, but I honestly don’t know. Also, in addition to valid and invalid, could you explain why that is the case? Thanks!







validity






share|improve this question









New contributor




A. Delarge is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.











share|improve this question









New contributor




A. Delarge is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.









share|improve this question




share|improve this question








edited 4 hours ago









virmaior

24.8k33995




24.8k33995






New contributor




A. Delarge is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.









asked 5 hours ago









A. DelargeA. Delarge

112




112




New contributor




A. Delarge is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.





New contributor





A. Delarge is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.






A. Delarge is a new contributor to this site. Take care in asking for clarification, commenting, and answering.
Check out our Code of Conduct.













  • Neither term in the conclusion appears in the premises. It looks like the relationship of the premises to the conclusion is irrelevancy.

    – Mark Andrews
    4 hours ago



















  • Neither term in the conclusion appears in the premises. It looks like the relationship of the premises to the conclusion is irrelevancy.

    – Mark Andrews
    4 hours ago

















Neither term in the conclusion appears in the premises. It looks like the relationship of the premises to the conclusion is irrelevancy.

– Mark Andrews
4 hours ago





Neither term in the conclusion appears in the premises. It looks like the relationship of the premises to the conclusion is irrelevancy.

– Mark Andrews
4 hours ago










2 Answers
2






active

oldest

votes


















2














This argument is valid on most definitions of validity.



The common definition of validity in use today is: if the premises are true, then the conclusion must be true.



worded another way, there must be no possible way for it to have all true premises and a false conclusion.



The value of validity (on this definition) is that it checks whether an argument is truth-preserving -- i.e. if you make all of its premises true, would the conclusion then also be true?



The argument you're looking at depends on a trick in the definition of validity: In your argument, it is impossible for all of the premises to be true at the same time because 1. S or R and 2. not S and not R are contradictory premises. Since you can never construct a case where you made all premises true and the conclusion false, it is never the case all true premises gives you a false conclusion (because it is never the case that there are all true premises).



The validity of this argument relates to the principle of explosion since once we've hit a contradiction, all the rules are out the window.



A second and pedagogically important point is that even though in common parlance: "good" , "sound", "valid", "strong", "clear" and many other words have similar seeming meanings, in logic, they each have a distinct meaning.



An argument of this form is valid but it's not really a good argument, because as Mark Andrews points there's no relation between these premises and this conclusion.





If you're doing some rather advanced logic (not your first course in formal logic or critical thinking), you may run into other definition of validity. On some of these, this argument fails, because you cannot construct a model with these premises and this conclusion. But this isn't your garden-variety definition.






share|improve this answer































    1














    I agree with @virmaior's answer.



    The results of this proof checker confirm the validity of the argument:



    enter image description here



    Line 4 is obtained from disjunctive syllogism (DS) on lines 1 and 2. See section 16.2 in forallx. Line 5 introduces a contradiction from lines 3 and 4. Line 6 comes from explosion (X) from line 5.



    For explosion, see page 119 in forallx. Here is the authors' motivation for that rule:




    It is a kind of elimination rule for ‘⊥’,
    and known as explosion. If we obtain a contradiction, symbolized by ‘⊥’, then we can infer whatever we like. How can this
    be motivated, as a rule of argumentation? Well, consider the English rhetorical device ‘. . . and if that’s true, I’ll eat my hat’. Since
    contradictions simply cannot be true, if one is true then not only
    will I eat my hat, I’ll have it too.






    Kevin Klement's JavaScript/PHP Fitch-style natural deduction proof editor and checker http://proofs.openlogicproject.org/



    P. D. Magnus, Tim Button with additions by J. Robert Loftis remixed and revised by Aaron Thomas-Bolduc, Richard Zach, forallx Calgary Remix: An Introduction to Formal Logic, Winter 2018. http://forallx.openlogicproject.org/






    share|improve this answer























      Your Answer








      StackExchange.ready(function() {
      var channelOptions = {
      tags: "".split(" "),
      id: "265"
      };
      initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

      StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
      // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
      if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
      StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
      createEditor();
      });
      }
      else {
      createEditor();
      }
      });

      function createEditor() {
      StackExchange.prepareEditor({
      heartbeatType: 'answer',
      autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
      convertImagesToLinks: false,
      noModals: true,
      showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
      reputationToPostImages: null,
      bindNavPrevention: true,
      postfix: "",
      imageUploader: {
      brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
      contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
      allowUrls: true
      },
      noCode: true, onDemand: true,
      discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
      ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
      });


      }
      });






      A. Delarge is a new contributor. Be nice, and check out our Code of Conduct.










      draft saved

      draft discarded


















      StackExchange.ready(
      function () {
      StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fphilosophy.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f60159%2fvalid-or-invalid-s-or-r-not-s-and-not-r-ergo-b%23new-answer', 'question_page');
      }
      );

      Post as a guest















      Required, but never shown

























      2 Answers
      2






      active

      oldest

      votes








      2 Answers
      2






      active

      oldest

      votes









      active

      oldest

      votes






      active

      oldest

      votes









      2














      This argument is valid on most definitions of validity.



      The common definition of validity in use today is: if the premises are true, then the conclusion must be true.



      worded another way, there must be no possible way for it to have all true premises and a false conclusion.



      The value of validity (on this definition) is that it checks whether an argument is truth-preserving -- i.e. if you make all of its premises true, would the conclusion then also be true?



      The argument you're looking at depends on a trick in the definition of validity: In your argument, it is impossible for all of the premises to be true at the same time because 1. S or R and 2. not S and not R are contradictory premises. Since you can never construct a case where you made all premises true and the conclusion false, it is never the case all true premises gives you a false conclusion (because it is never the case that there are all true premises).



      The validity of this argument relates to the principle of explosion since once we've hit a contradiction, all the rules are out the window.



      A second and pedagogically important point is that even though in common parlance: "good" , "sound", "valid", "strong", "clear" and many other words have similar seeming meanings, in logic, they each have a distinct meaning.



      An argument of this form is valid but it's not really a good argument, because as Mark Andrews points there's no relation between these premises and this conclusion.





      If you're doing some rather advanced logic (not your first course in formal logic or critical thinking), you may run into other definition of validity. On some of these, this argument fails, because you cannot construct a model with these premises and this conclusion. But this isn't your garden-variety definition.






      share|improve this answer




























        2














        This argument is valid on most definitions of validity.



        The common definition of validity in use today is: if the premises are true, then the conclusion must be true.



        worded another way, there must be no possible way for it to have all true premises and a false conclusion.



        The value of validity (on this definition) is that it checks whether an argument is truth-preserving -- i.e. if you make all of its premises true, would the conclusion then also be true?



        The argument you're looking at depends on a trick in the definition of validity: In your argument, it is impossible for all of the premises to be true at the same time because 1. S or R and 2. not S and not R are contradictory premises. Since you can never construct a case where you made all premises true and the conclusion false, it is never the case all true premises gives you a false conclusion (because it is never the case that there are all true premises).



        The validity of this argument relates to the principle of explosion since once we've hit a contradiction, all the rules are out the window.



        A second and pedagogically important point is that even though in common parlance: "good" , "sound", "valid", "strong", "clear" and many other words have similar seeming meanings, in logic, they each have a distinct meaning.



        An argument of this form is valid but it's not really a good argument, because as Mark Andrews points there's no relation between these premises and this conclusion.





        If you're doing some rather advanced logic (not your first course in formal logic or critical thinking), you may run into other definition of validity. On some of these, this argument fails, because you cannot construct a model with these premises and this conclusion. But this isn't your garden-variety definition.






        share|improve this answer


























          2












          2








          2







          This argument is valid on most definitions of validity.



          The common definition of validity in use today is: if the premises are true, then the conclusion must be true.



          worded another way, there must be no possible way for it to have all true premises and a false conclusion.



          The value of validity (on this definition) is that it checks whether an argument is truth-preserving -- i.e. if you make all of its premises true, would the conclusion then also be true?



          The argument you're looking at depends on a trick in the definition of validity: In your argument, it is impossible for all of the premises to be true at the same time because 1. S or R and 2. not S and not R are contradictory premises. Since you can never construct a case where you made all premises true and the conclusion false, it is never the case all true premises gives you a false conclusion (because it is never the case that there are all true premises).



          The validity of this argument relates to the principle of explosion since once we've hit a contradiction, all the rules are out the window.



          A second and pedagogically important point is that even though in common parlance: "good" , "sound", "valid", "strong", "clear" and many other words have similar seeming meanings, in logic, they each have a distinct meaning.



          An argument of this form is valid but it's not really a good argument, because as Mark Andrews points there's no relation between these premises and this conclusion.





          If you're doing some rather advanced logic (not your first course in formal logic or critical thinking), you may run into other definition of validity. On some of these, this argument fails, because you cannot construct a model with these premises and this conclusion. But this isn't your garden-variety definition.






          share|improve this answer













          This argument is valid on most definitions of validity.



          The common definition of validity in use today is: if the premises are true, then the conclusion must be true.



          worded another way, there must be no possible way for it to have all true premises and a false conclusion.



          The value of validity (on this definition) is that it checks whether an argument is truth-preserving -- i.e. if you make all of its premises true, would the conclusion then also be true?



          The argument you're looking at depends on a trick in the definition of validity: In your argument, it is impossible for all of the premises to be true at the same time because 1. S or R and 2. not S and not R are contradictory premises. Since you can never construct a case where you made all premises true and the conclusion false, it is never the case all true premises gives you a false conclusion (because it is never the case that there are all true premises).



          The validity of this argument relates to the principle of explosion since once we've hit a contradiction, all the rules are out the window.



          A second and pedagogically important point is that even though in common parlance: "good" , "sound", "valid", "strong", "clear" and many other words have similar seeming meanings, in logic, they each have a distinct meaning.



          An argument of this form is valid but it's not really a good argument, because as Mark Andrews points there's no relation between these premises and this conclusion.





          If you're doing some rather advanced logic (not your first course in formal logic or critical thinking), you may run into other definition of validity. On some of these, this argument fails, because you cannot construct a model with these premises and this conclusion. But this isn't your garden-variety definition.







          share|improve this answer












          share|improve this answer



          share|improve this answer










          answered 4 hours ago









          virmaiorvirmaior

          24.8k33995




          24.8k33995























              1














              I agree with @virmaior's answer.



              The results of this proof checker confirm the validity of the argument:



              enter image description here



              Line 4 is obtained from disjunctive syllogism (DS) on lines 1 and 2. See section 16.2 in forallx. Line 5 introduces a contradiction from lines 3 and 4. Line 6 comes from explosion (X) from line 5.



              For explosion, see page 119 in forallx. Here is the authors' motivation for that rule:




              It is a kind of elimination rule for ‘⊥’,
              and known as explosion. If we obtain a contradiction, symbolized by ‘⊥’, then we can infer whatever we like. How can this
              be motivated, as a rule of argumentation? Well, consider the English rhetorical device ‘. . . and if that’s true, I’ll eat my hat’. Since
              contradictions simply cannot be true, if one is true then not only
              will I eat my hat, I’ll have it too.






              Kevin Klement's JavaScript/PHP Fitch-style natural deduction proof editor and checker http://proofs.openlogicproject.org/



              P. D. Magnus, Tim Button with additions by J. Robert Loftis remixed and revised by Aaron Thomas-Bolduc, Richard Zach, forallx Calgary Remix: An Introduction to Formal Logic, Winter 2018. http://forallx.openlogicproject.org/






              share|improve this answer




























                1














                I agree with @virmaior's answer.



                The results of this proof checker confirm the validity of the argument:



                enter image description here



                Line 4 is obtained from disjunctive syllogism (DS) on lines 1 and 2. See section 16.2 in forallx. Line 5 introduces a contradiction from lines 3 and 4. Line 6 comes from explosion (X) from line 5.



                For explosion, see page 119 in forallx. Here is the authors' motivation for that rule:




                It is a kind of elimination rule for ‘⊥’,
                and known as explosion. If we obtain a contradiction, symbolized by ‘⊥’, then we can infer whatever we like. How can this
                be motivated, as a rule of argumentation? Well, consider the English rhetorical device ‘. . . and if that’s true, I’ll eat my hat’. Since
                contradictions simply cannot be true, if one is true then not only
                will I eat my hat, I’ll have it too.






                Kevin Klement's JavaScript/PHP Fitch-style natural deduction proof editor and checker http://proofs.openlogicproject.org/



                P. D. Magnus, Tim Button with additions by J. Robert Loftis remixed and revised by Aaron Thomas-Bolduc, Richard Zach, forallx Calgary Remix: An Introduction to Formal Logic, Winter 2018. http://forallx.openlogicproject.org/






                share|improve this answer


























                  1












                  1








                  1







                  I agree with @virmaior's answer.



                  The results of this proof checker confirm the validity of the argument:



                  enter image description here



                  Line 4 is obtained from disjunctive syllogism (DS) on lines 1 and 2. See section 16.2 in forallx. Line 5 introduces a contradiction from lines 3 and 4. Line 6 comes from explosion (X) from line 5.



                  For explosion, see page 119 in forallx. Here is the authors' motivation for that rule:




                  It is a kind of elimination rule for ‘⊥’,
                  and known as explosion. If we obtain a contradiction, symbolized by ‘⊥’, then we can infer whatever we like. How can this
                  be motivated, as a rule of argumentation? Well, consider the English rhetorical device ‘. . . and if that’s true, I’ll eat my hat’. Since
                  contradictions simply cannot be true, if one is true then not only
                  will I eat my hat, I’ll have it too.






                  Kevin Klement's JavaScript/PHP Fitch-style natural deduction proof editor and checker http://proofs.openlogicproject.org/



                  P. D. Magnus, Tim Button with additions by J. Robert Loftis remixed and revised by Aaron Thomas-Bolduc, Richard Zach, forallx Calgary Remix: An Introduction to Formal Logic, Winter 2018. http://forallx.openlogicproject.org/






                  share|improve this answer













                  I agree with @virmaior's answer.



                  The results of this proof checker confirm the validity of the argument:



                  enter image description here



                  Line 4 is obtained from disjunctive syllogism (DS) on lines 1 and 2. See section 16.2 in forallx. Line 5 introduces a contradiction from lines 3 and 4. Line 6 comes from explosion (X) from line 5.



                  For explosion, see page 119 in forallx. Here is the authors' motivation for that rule:




                  It is a kind of elimination rule for ‘⊥’,
                  and known as explosion. If we obtain a contradiction, symbolized by ‘⊥’, then we can infer whatever we like. How can this
                  be motivated, as a rule of argumentation? Well, consider the English rhetorical device ‘. . . and if that’s true, I’ll eat my hat’. Since
                  contradictions simply cannot be true, if one is true then not only
                  will I eat my hat, I’ll have it too.






                  Kevin Klement's JavaScript/PHP Fitch-style natural deduction proof editor and checker http://proofs.openlogicproject.org/



                  P. D. Magnus, Tim Button with additions by J. Robert Loftis remixed and revised by Aaron Thomas-Bolduc, Richard Zach, forallx Calgary Remix: An Introduction to Formal Logic, Winter 2018. http://forallx.openlogicproject.org/







                  share|improve this answer












                  share|improve this answer



                  share|improve this answer










                  answered 1 hour ago









                  Frank HubenyFrank Hubeny

                  7,96251447




                  7,96251447






















                      A. Delarge is a new contributor. Be nice, and check out our Code of Conduct.










                      draft saved

                      draft discarded


















                      A. Delarge is a new contributor. Be nice, and check out our Code of Conduct.













                      A. Delarge is a new contributor. Be nice, and check out our Code of Conduct.












                      A. Delarge is a new contributor. Be nice, and check out our Code of Conduct.
















                      Thanks for contributing an answer to Philosophy Stack Exchange!


                      • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

                      But avoid



                      • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

                      • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.


                      To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.




                      draft saved


                      draft discarded














                      StackExchange.ready(
                      function () {
                      StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fphilosophy.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f60159%2fvalid-or-invalid-s-or-r-not-s-and-not-r-ergo-b%23new-answer', 'question_page');
                      }
                      );

                      Post as a guest















                      Required, but never shown





















































                      Required, but never shown














                      Required, but never shown












                      Required, but never shown







                      Required, but never shown

































                      Required, but never shown














                      Required, but never shown












                      Required, but never shown







                      Required, but never shown







                      Popular posts from this blog

                      flock() on closed filehandle LOCK_FILE at /usr/bin/apt-mirror

                      Mangá

                      Eduardo VII do Reino Unido